Difference between revisions of "Notes:Quotient topology"
(Created page with "'''Note to readers: ''' the page quotient topology as it stands right now ({{subst:CurrentTime}}) is an embarrassment to me. However before I can clean it up I must unify...") |
m (→According to John M. Lee) |
||
(8 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
− | '''Note to readers: ''' the page [[quotient topology]] as it stands right now ( | + | : '''Note to readers: ''' the page [[quotient topology]] as it stands right now ([[User:Alec|Alec]] ([[User talk:Alec|talk]]) 17:07, 21 April 2016 (UTC)) is an embarrassment to me. However before I can clean it up I must unify it. I've been using it for almost 2 years now though I promise! Gosh this is embarrassing. |
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | See [[Notes:Quotient topology plan]] for an outline of the page. | ||
+ | __TOC__ | ||
==According to John M. Lee== | ==According to John M. Lee== | ||
+ | : '''Addendum: ''' for some reason I lie here, the author considers a map {{M|f:X\rightarrow A}} where {{M|A}} is a [[set]] and later applies the equivalence relation version to it. | ||
Let {{M|\sim}} denote an [[equivalence relation]], let {{M|(X,\mathcal{J})}} be a [[topological space]]. We get a map, {{M|\pi:X\rightarrow\frac{X}{\sim} }} that takes {{M|\pi:x\rightarrow[x]}} | Let {{M|\sim}} denote an [[equivalence relation]], let {{M|(X,\mathcal{J})}} be a [[topological space]]. We get a map, {{M|\pi:X\rightarrow\frac{X}{\sim} }} that takes {{M|\pi:x\rightarrow[x]}} | ||
* The quotient topology on {{M|\frac{X}{\sim} }} is the [[finer topology|finest]] such that {{M|\pi}} is [[continuous]] | * The quotient topology on {{M|\frac{X}{\sim} }} is the [[finer topology|finest]] such that {{M|\pi}} is [[continuous]] | ||
Line 13: | Line 18: | ||
Lee actually defines the quotient topology using maps first, then constructs the equiv relation version, but we can can define an equivalence relation as follows: | Lee actually defines the quotient topology using maps first, then constructs the equiv relation version, but we can can define an equivalence relation as follows: | ||
* {{M|1=x\sim y\iff q(x)=q(y)}} and that's where this comes from | * {{M|1=x\sim y\iff q(x)=q(y)}} and that's where this comes from | ||
+ | ===Passing to the quotient=== | ||
+ | <div style="float:right;margin:0.1em;"> | ||
+ | {| class="wikitable" border="1" | ||
+ | |- | ||
+ | |<center><span style="font-size:1.2em;"><m>\xymatrix{ | ||
+ | X \ar[d]_q \ar[dr]^f & \\ | ||
+ | Y \ar@{.>}[r]_{\bar{f}} & Z | ||
+ | }</m></span></center> | ||
+ | |- | ||
+ | ! Passing to the quotient | ||
+ | |} | ||
+ | </div>This is very similar to [[quotient (function)|the quotient of a function]].<br/> | ||
+ | * Let X and Z be [[topological space|topological space|topological spaces]], | ||
+ | * let {{M|q:X\rightarrow Y}} be a quotient map, | ||
+ | * let {{M|f:X\rightarrow Z}} be ''any'' continuous mapping such that {{M|1=q(x)=q(y)\implies f(x)=f(y)}} | ||
+ | Then | ||
+ | * There exists a unique continuous map, {{M|\bar{f}:Y\rightarrow Z}} such that {{M|1=f=\bar{f}\circ q}} | ||
+ | |||
==Munkres== | ==Munkres== | ||
+ | '''Munkres starts with a quotient map''' | ||
+ | * Let {{M|(X,\mathcal{J})}} and {{M|(Y,\mathcal{K})}} be [[topological space|topological spaces]] and | ||
+ | * let {{M|q:X\rightarrow Y}} be a [[surjective]] map | ||
+ | We say {{M|q}} is a ''quotient map'' provided: | ||
+ | * {{M|\forall U\in\mathcal{P}(Y)[U\in\mathcal{K}\iff p^{-1}(U)\in\mathcal{J}]}} | ||
+ | He goes on to say: | ||
+ | # This condition is "stronger than continuity" (of {{M|q}} presumably) probably because if we gave {{M|Y}} the [[indiscrete topology]] it'd be continuous. | ||
+ | # He defines this in several ways, one of which is "saturation" of maps. Yeah this is just the [[equivalence relation]] version hiding (CHECK THIS THOUGH) | ||
+ | ===Quotient topology=== | ||
+ | If {{M|(X,\mathcal{J})}} is a [[topological space]] and {{M|A}} a [[set]] and if {{M|p:X\rightarrow A}} is a ''[[surjective]]'' [[map]] then: | ||
+ | * There is exactly on topology, {{M|\mathcal{K} }} on {{M|A}} relative to which {{M|p}} is a ''quotient map'' (as defined above) | ||
+ | That topology is the ''quotient topology'' induced by {{M|p}} | ||
+ | ===Quotient space=== | ||
+ | Let {{M|(X,\mathcal{J})}} be a [[topological space]] and let {{M|X^*}} be a [[partition]] of {{M|X}} into disjoint subsets whose union is {{M|X}} (that is the definition of a [[partition]]). | ||
+ | Let {{M|p:X\rightarrow X^*}} be the surjective map that carries each point of {{M|X}} to the element of {{M|X^*}} containing that point, then: | ||
+ | * The ''quotient topology'' induced by {{M|p}} on {{M|X^*}} is called the ''quotient space'' of {{M|X}} | ||
+ | ==Mond== | ||
+ | : '''Note: ''' David Mond is my tutor at university. While I ''do not'' like his style of writing (informal definitions, ambiguities in the ''English'' interpretation) he does have a great way of ordering things. That is applicable here. I also found like 9 typos in the first 8 pages; however it has many examples and many pictures, and they are lecture notes. | ||
+ | Mond starts with a [[topological space]] {{M|(X,\mathcal{J})}} and an [[equivalence relation]], {{M|\sim}}. Then: | ||
+ | * The ''quotient topology'' ({{M|\mathcal{K} }}) on {{M|\frac{X}{\sim} }} is the topology where {{M|\forall U\in\mathcal{P}(\frac{X}{\sim})[U\in\mathcal{K}\iff \pi^{-1}(U)\in\mathcal{J}]}} | ||
+ | ===Passing to the quotient=== | ||
+ | Mond then goes for passing to the quotient, exactly as John M. Lee has. Very weirdly worded though. | ||
+ | |||
+ | No mention of the ''quotient map'' as a concept. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Deals with [[equivalence relation generated by]] which is great. | ||
+ | ==Mendelson== | ||
+ | Starts with what is called a ''quotient map'' above, but calls it "an identification". Then he goes straight on to "passing to the quotient" it's a very weirdly written section, but he does: | ||
+ | # Identification map | ||
+ | # Identification topology | ||
+ | It seems I'll have to prove these concepts are the same (having one induces the other). Provides a source for the "identification" terminology, which is useful. | ||
+ | ==Gamelin & Greene== | ||
+ | # Quotient topology, given a [[topological space]] {{M|(X,\mathcal{J})}} and a set {{M|Y}}, as usual. | ||
+ | # Slightly strange, again top space {{M|(X,\mathcal{J})}} and an equivalence relation {{M|\sim}}, for {{M|f:\frac{X}{\sim}\rightarrow Y}} - {{M|f}} is continuous {{M|\iff}} {{M|f\circ\pi}} is continuous ({{M|\pi}} being the canonical projection) | ||
+ | #* This is NOT passing to the quotient | ||
+ | # Passing to the quotient now. Let {{M|f:X\rightarrow Y}} be continuous function, and {{M|\sim}} and equivalence relation on {{M|X}} such that {{M|f}} is constant for each {{M|x\in[x]\in\frac{X}{\sim} }}. Then: | ||
+ | #* {{M|\exists g:\frac{X}{\sim}\rightarrow Y}} continuous such that {{M|1=f=g\circ\pi}} |
Latest revision as of 19:45, 26 April 2016
- Note to readers: the page quotient topology as it stands right now (Alec (talk) 17:07, 21 April 2016 (UTC)) is an embarrassment to me. However before I can clean it up I must unify it. I've been using it for almost 2 years now though I promise! Gosh this is embarrassing.
See Notes:Quotient topology plan for an outline of the page.
Contents
[hide]According to John M. Lee
- Addendum: for some reason I lie here, the author considers a map f:X→A where A is a set and later applies the equivalence relation version to it.
Let ∼ denote an equivalence relation, let (X,J) be a topological space. We get a map, π:X→X∼ that takes π:x→[x]
- The quotient topology on X∼ is the finest such that π is continuous
Let K denote a topology on X∼, then we may define K as:
- K:={U∈P(X∼) | π−1(U)∈J}, that is:
- U∈P(X∼) is open if π−1(U) is open in X - we get "only if" by going the other way. I must make a page about how definitions are "iff"s
Note: more than one book is very clear on "U∈P(X∼) is open in X∼ if and only if π−1(U)∈J, not sure why they stress it so.
Quotient map
A map between two topological spaces (X,J) and (Y,K) is a quotient map if:
- It is surjective
- The topology on Y (K) is the quotient topology that'd be induced on Y by the map q
Lee actually defines the quotient topology using maps first, then constructs the equiv relation version, but we can can define an equivalence relation as follows:
- x∼y⟺q(x)=q(y) and that's where this comes from
Passing to the quotient
Passing to the quotient |
---|
- Let X and Z be topological space|topological spaces,
- let q:X→Y be a quotient map,
- let f:X→Z be any continuous mapping such that q(x)=q(y)⟹f(x)=f(y)
Then
- There exists a unique continuous map, ˉf:Y→Z such that f=ˉf∘q
Munkres
Munkres starts with a quotient map
- Let (X,J) and (Y,K) be topological spaces and
- let q:X→Y be a surjective map
We say q is a quotient map provided:
- ∀U∈P(Y)[U∈K⟺p−1(U)∈J]
He goes on to say:
- This condition is "stronger than continuity" (of q presumably) probably because if we gave Y the indiscrete topology it'd be continuous.
- He defines this in several ways, one of which is "saturation" of maps. Yeah this is just the equivalence relation version hiding (CHECK THIS THOUGH)
Quotient topology
If (X,J) is a topological space and A a set and if p:X→A is a surjective map then:
- There is exactly on topology, K on A relative to which p is a quotient map (as defined above)
That topology is the quotient topology induced by p
Quotient space
Let (X,J) be a topological space and let X∗ be a partition of X into disjoint subsets whose union is X (that is the definition of a partition). Let p:X→X∗ be the surjective map that carries each point of X to the element of X∗ containing that point, then:
- The quotient topology induced by p on X∗ is called the quotient space of X
Mond
- Note: David Mond is my tutor at university. While I do not like his style of writing (informal definitions, ambiguities in the English interpretation) he does have a great way of ordering things. That is applicable here. I also found like 9 typos in the first 8 pages; however it has many examples and many pictures, and they are lecture notes.
Mond starts with a topological space (X,J) and an equivalence relation, ∼. Then:
- The quotient topology (K) on X∼ is the topology where ∀U∈P(X∼)[U∈K⟺π−1(U)∈J]
Passing to the quotient
Mond then goes for passing to the quotient, exactly as John M. Lee has. Very weirdly worded though.
No mention of the quotient map as a concept.
Deals with equivalence relation generated by which is great.
Mendelson
Starts with what is called a quotient map above, but calls it "an identification". Then he goes straight on to "passing to the quotient" it's a very weirdly written section, but he does:
- Identification map
- Identification topology
It seems I'll have to prove these concepts are the same (having one induces the other). Provides a source for the "identification" terminology, which is useful.
Gamelin & Greene
- Quotient topology, given a topological space (X,J) and a set Y, as usual.
- Slightly strange, again top space (X,J) and an equivalence relation ∼, for f:X∼→Y - f is continuous ⟺ f∘π is continuous (π being the canonical projection)
- This is NOT passing to the quotient
- Passing to the quotient now. Let f:X→Y be continuous function, and ∼ and equivalence relation on X such that f is constant for each x∈[x]∈X∼. Then:
- ∃g:X∼→Y continuous such that f=g∘π